J. Paleont. 62(3), 1988, pp. 319-329
Copyright ©1998. The Paleontological Society
0022-3360/88/0062-0319$03.00

PRESIDENTIAL ADDRESS

TRENDS AS CHANGES IN VARIANCE: A NEW SLANT ON
PROGRESS AND DIRECTIONALITY IN EVOLUTION

STEPHEN JAY GOULD
Museum of Comparative Zoology, Harvard University, Cambridge, Massachusetts 02138


ABSTRACT-Trends are the primary phenomenon of macroevolution, but they have often been misinterpreted because an old and deep conceptual error has induced us to misread, as anagenesis in abstracted entities, a pattern that actually records changes in variance by increase or decrease in diversity or disparity among species within clades. These patterns are actually produced by the "entity making and breaking machine" of differential species success, but we misread history as anagenesis because we focus on extreme values (though they may only represent tails in variance of a system), or on measures of central tendency that shift passively as species birth and death work in their differential way. I discuss several examples in two classes: "increase trends mediated by growth in variance, and "decrease trends" produced by diminution of diversity or disparity. I present two examples in extenso based on original data: threefold occurrence of Cope's rule in planktonic foraminifers as a consequence of increasing species diversity from small founding lineages (increase trend), and disappearance of. 400 hitting in baseball as a decrease trend recording symmetrical decline of variance with increasing excellence of play, not the gradual extinction of a valued "thing." A proper appreciation of trends as changes in variance flows from and into the two most important revisionary themes in modern evolutionary theory: 1) constraint and structure as an antidote to overreliance upon adaptation (questions about why founding lineages tend to be small, and why size ranges are constrained, lie primarily in structural, not adaptational, domains); 2) hierarchy (increase and decrease trends are powered by differential species sorting not by extrapolated anagenesis of competition among organisms within populations)


INTRODUCTION

G EOLOGISTS, with good humor, have tried to enliven the Latin mottoes that still emblazon the professional logos of academe. The International Geological Congress, in pleasant alliteration, proclaims mente et malleo--with mind and hammer. Our Society uses a different version of the same idea, in the even more iconoclastic form of an unabashed, but sublime, joke: frango ut patefaciam--I break in order to reveal.

The statement, no doubt, was meant literally as a reference to Estwings and bedding planes. But I suggest that we might also find some inspiration in a metaphorical meaning. The greatest impediments to scientific progress are often conceptual locks, not factual lacks. The missing pieces of a puzzle may well deprive us of an adequate solution, but a far more serious bar to understanding lies in mental frameworks that limit conceivable solutions to a restricted, and false, subset of larger possibilities. When we think that we proceed with absolute and comprehensive objectivity, we are even more likely to be lost, for then we unconsciously cloak our own disabling biases and sally forth down a primrose path masquerading as the straight and narrow road to final truth.
 
Gunnar Myrdal, the Swedish historian and sociologist who wrote the greatest book on American racism (An American Dilemma. 1944), expressed this fundamental quandry of intellectual life in writing:

There must be ... countless errors ... that no living man can yet detect, because of the fog within which our type of Western culture envelops us. Cultural influences have set up the assumptions about the mind, the body, and the universe with which we begin; pose the questions we ask; influence the facts we seek; determine the interpretation we give these facts; and direct our reaction to these interpretations and conclusions.

We must break conceptual bonds, not only rocks, if we wish to understand the history of life.

I propose, in this address, that we reexamine the conceptual basis of evolutionary trends--the key phenomenon behind a century of claims (or denials) that life's history provides a unique and essential input to biological theory. I suggest that the most important contemporary revision of evolutionary theory--the insight that selection (and other forces) acts simultaneously at several levels of a genealogical hierarchy, with effects propagating to levels above and below--might also reorient our interpretation of evolutionary trends.
 
The traditional view depicts trends as a product of anagenetic change within lineages. What else could a trend be? You have to get from here to there through steps in between, don't you?1 This conventional reading reflects two central beliefs that are rarely questioned or even stated: first, that trends are powered by entities either rolling or pushed in certain directions; second, that the motor of pushing shall be found in ordinary Darwinian forces of selection and competition. Thus, an environmental change from woodlands to grasslands, and a subsequent shift of optimal eating strategies from browsing to grazing powered the most famous of all evolutionary sequences-the linear museum parade of Hyracotherium to Equus. And the adaptive benefits of mentality marked the ascent from Australopithecus through primitive species of Homo to our exalted selves. (Professionals, of course, recognize the bushiness of equid and hominid trees, but still view the lone survivors as end-products of a coherent anagenetic sequence within the bush.) Similar anagenetic interpretations apply to changes in habitat as well as form:

____________________

1 The annual symposium of the Paleontological Society directly proceeded the luncheon at which I delivered this Presidential Address on Tuesday, October 27, 1987. Devoted to evolutionary trends, this symposium beautifully illustrated my claim about conceptual locks. All speakers, with the sole exception of Steve Stanley, treated trends as anagenetic sequences only. Many elegant techniques were presented for assessing variations in rate within such sequences, but no one even suggested that what we perceive as trends may be produced by other processes (proliferation rather than directed motion), or that such anagenetic accumulations might play little part in the sum total of changing character gradients within clades.

319


141